Usually the statement that you’ve read nine books by a
single author is read as a boast. Not so if the author in question is
philosopher Nicholas Rescher, whose list of published books exceeds one hundred
and sixty.
Allow me to repeat that in case you think
it’s a typo. Nicholas Rescher, Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at the University of
Pittsburgh, approaching his eighty-ninth year, has written a hundred and sixty
books (a conservative count that excludes his own translations of other work
and compilations of collected works by others). In 2010 alone, when he was
eighty-two years old, Rescher published thirteen books. In 2016 he let down the
team by only publishing four books. Loser.
This prodigious, perhaps insane, productivity is I think
casually passed over by commentators as an interesting anecdote to inoculate them
from tearing their hair out. His Wikipedia page contains the joke that is
passed around about Rescher that he is not one person but a committee. Or maybe
five committees. The blatant unnaturalness of his bibliography (including
approximately four hundred articles) is best dealt with by downgrading it to
the status of a quirk.
Pictures of the man show the object of benevolence itself
with requisite bald head and accountant’s attire, plus a wry half-smile to let the photographer know that he would like to leave and write two more books before afternoon
tea.
Comfortably installed at the University of Pittsburgh since 1961, Rescher’s
range has been predictably large and multifaceted over the course of sixty years. His early work concerned Arabic philosophy, he's co-invented a particular
method of forecasting, and as well as contributing to pretty much every major issue in
contemporary philosophy has written popular works on issues such as luck, risk,
prediction, altruism, welfare and, most recently how to compose intelligence reports(?).
There doesn’t seem to be anything that unifies Rescher’s
work more aptly than a stunningly omnivorous curiosity about the world and the
life of ideas. Calling himself both a pragmatist in the classic American
tradition of Charles Sanders Peirce and my namesake, combined with a taste for
the now-largely-discredited strain of philosophical idealism of Germany,
Rescher opens the most revealing portal on what he truly cares about whenever
he discusses the human striving for knowledge and the many complications and struggles that hinder this enterprise.
What I’ve read of Rescher’s work only provides me with a fraction
of his many interests. Nonetheless this preoccupation with knowledge
acquisition can be detected as occupying the central place in his oeuvre. Take
my favourite book so far among Rescher’s: The
Strife of Systems, an account of the bountiful diversity of philosophical
systems throughout history. Rescher sets
the scene of investigation in an enticing manner when he notes that all major
philosophical systems are constructed with the purpose of putting an end to philosophical
activity (by finally providing the appropriate tools to root out ambiguity),
while here we are two thousand years later, still philosophizing.
The answer to this paradox isn’t that philosophy is more
complex than other intellectual endeavours. Rather it is to do with the nature
of philosophizing itself, which is to say it is to do with the nature of
argumentation in life generally. Homo sapiens argue about life and love, means
and ends, but never to a conclusion that will objectively satisfy all. Rescher
propounds an orientational pluralism,
a type of pluralism that prevents the individual from succumbing to relativism by
admitting the possibility of objective truth but without admitting of objective
agreement. The possibilities and limitations of the human condition permit us
to maintain the truth as we see it but remove the possibility of getting others
on board. ‘Orientational pluralism is’, Rescher writes, ‘… a pluralism that
fragments matters. But what it fragments is not reality or truth, but
justification’.
While on the one hand Rescher’s task has been to inject a
sense of realism into the philosophical enterprise, on the other he is a
sincere and forceful defender of philosophy. Rescher’s most common line,
repeated throughout his books, is that we have questions and need answers. This
is the centre of his work. The love of wisdom starts with curiosity. A thinker
like John Ralston Saul complained on the last page of Voltaire’s Bastards that Western civilization had become too
preoccupied with answers at the expense of simply asking questions, and this
had resulted in the development of technocracy and decline in humanistic values.
But this would be taking it too far for Rescher. By definition inquiring humans
need some of the symmetry afforded by concluding their inquiries, however
provisionally and subject to modification they are.
The strategies we employ to satisfy our hunger for knowledge
while admitting of the various limitations in our capacity to do so have been plentifully
categorised by Rescher throughout his career. Suffice it to say that his
rigorous approach does not allow for laziness, fuzzy thinking or half-hearted
answers. Reading Rescher is a great introduction to how a philosopher
approaches an issue: defining terms, making distinctions, presenting
possible objections, looking from multiple angles, marshalling analogies and
reaching the most plausible conclusion given the reasoning involved. It also
helps that Rescher’s writing style is a model of clarity and lack of
pretension, with the occasional striking aphoristic phrase.
But a question I certainly have in relation to Rescher’s
output is whether the number of concerns and ideas is equal to the amount of
books produced. The answer is probably no. Repetitions abound in Rescher’s
books, not simply of themes and passages but of exact phrases. One of the
reasons I could never get into Thorstein Veblen was precisely his tendency to
consistently repeat phrases verbatim as if the reader hadn’t yet come across
them. This despite him constantly being touted as an original and underappreciated
writer.
Rescher’s concerns sure seem inexhaustible, but they are
ultimately outnumbered by his publications. I can easily image a career where
his output is cut in half and him still having the same impact. Having said
this, repetition is often justified by the fact that as a philosopher your
arguments must proceed by building one observation on top of another in linear
fashion, which requires a recapitulation of key themes. And besides, if like me
you appreciate the things being hammered home, then occasionally seeing them
repeated isn’t such a big deal. So as I embark on my tenth, eleventh and
twelfth Rescher books, the expectation that he’ll say something genuinely
surprising will gradually recede, but none the worse for that. An interesting
spin on a well-worn idea is better than forcing out half-baked concepts for the
sake of novelty.
The title of one of Rescher’s books is Human Interests, and there is no better description of his life’s
work. Philosophers are basically serious nerds, and he counts as one of the most
notorious. In recent years Rescher has given explicit confirmation of his nerd
status by building a replica of a ciphering machine first designed by the
polymath Gottfried Leibniz in the 1670s, using Leibniz’s own notes and memos as
a guide.
Thus our incomplete picture of this man can end with the observation that even if he were deprived of the opportunity to write more books, he could still find ways of remaining connected to his passion.
Thus our incomplete picture of this man can end with the observation that even if he were deprived of the opportunity to write more books, he could still find ways of remaining connected to his passion.
Comments